MATH 409 Lecture 4

From Notes
Jump to navigation Jump to search

« previous | Thursday, September 5, 2013 | next »

Lecture Slides

Solutions to Challenges

Challenge 2

Construct a strict linear order on the set such that implies for all

Given complex numbers and , where and . Define if:

  • and
  • and

Challenge 3

Construct a strict linear order on of rational functions in variable with real coefficients that makes into an ordered field.

Given rational functions , we let if there exists such that for all .

Showing strict order is easy, and verifying axioms of addition and multiplication is also easy. Hard part is proving linearity:

Assume and let . Then , where and are nonzero polynomials. Since any nonzero polynomial has only finitely many roots, there exists such that and have no roots in the interval . is continuous and nowhere zero on . Therefore it maintains its sign on this interval, i.e. either for all or for all . In the first case, . In the second case, .

Note: This field does not follow the Archimedean principle


General Intervals

Suppose is a stet endowed with a strict linear order .

A subset is called an interval if with any two elements it contains all elements of that lie between them. To be precise, and imply that for all .

Examples:

  • The empty set and all one-element subsets of are trivially intervals.
  • Open finite interval , where and .
  • Closed and semi-open intervals
  • Open semi-infinite intervals
    • , where .
  • Closed semi-infinite intervals
  • Complete infinite interval


Intervals of the Real Line

Theorem 1. Suppose is a bounded interval of that consists of more than one point. Then there exist with such that or or , or .

Theorem 2. Suppose is an interval of bounded above but unbounded below. Then such that or .

Theorem 3. Suppose is an interval of bounded below but unbounded above. Then such that or .

Theorem 4. Suppose is an interval of that is neither bounded above nor bounded below. Then .

Note: Next challenge: Prove theorems 1 and 4


Natural Numbers, Integers, and Rationals

A set is called inductive if and, for any real number , implies . The set of natural numbers is the smallest inductive subset of .

Note: The set is well defined. Namely, it is the intersection of all inductive subsets of .

Integers are defined as

Rationals are defined as


Properties of Natural Numbers

  • 1 is the least natural number: the interval is an inductive set. Hence .
  • If , then : Let be set of all such that . Then as . Besides, for any we have so that . Therefore is an inductive set. Then , which implies that .
more appropriately, that should be a ⊆
  • If , then the open interval contains no natural numbers: Let be the set of all such that . Then as . Now assume and take any . We have since , and since . By the above, . Thus is an inductive set, which implies .


Principle of Well-Ordering

Suppose is a set endowed with a strict linear order . We say that a subset is well-ordered with respect to if any nonempty subset of has a least element.

Theorem. The set is well-ordered with respect to the natural ordering of the real line .

Proof. Let be an arbitrary nonempty subset of . The set is bounded below since 1 is a lower bound of . Therefore exists. Since is a lower bound of while is not, we can find such that . As shown before, the interval is disjoint from . Then is disjoint from , which implies that is a lower bound of . Hence , so by weak antisymmetry. Thus is the least element of .


Principle of Mathematical Induction

Theorem. Let be an assertion depending on a natural variable . Suppose that

  • holds,
  • whenever holds, so does .

Then holds for all .

Proof. Let be the set of all natural numbers such that holds. Clearly is an inductive set. Therefore which implies that .

quod erat demonstrandum
Note: The assertion is called the basis of induction. The implication is called the induction step.

Examples of assertions :

  • is divisible by 6
  • for some

We can use mathematical induction for by starting with a different (shifted) base.


Strong Induction

Theorem. Let be an assertion depending on a natural variable . Suppose that holds whenever holds for all natural . Then holds for all .

In other words, for , the assuption of the theorem means that holds unconditionally. For , it means that implies . For , it means that and imply . And so on...

Proof. For any we define a new assertion " holds for any natural ". Then is equivalent to , in particular, it holds. By assumption implies for any . Moreover, holds if and only if both and hold. Therefore implies for all . By the principle of mathematical induction, holds for all and thus holds as well.

quod erat demonstrandum


Functions

A function (or map) is an assignment: to each we assign an element .

The graph of the function is defined as the subset of consisting of all pairs of the form for . Two functions are considered the same if their graphs coincide

Properties

A function is surjective (or onto) if for each , there exists at least one such that .

The function is injective (or one-to-one) if implies . This can be tested with a horizontal line on graph: for all horizontal lines, the graph of should intersect only once.

A function is bijective if and only if it is both injective and surjective.

Inverse Function

Suppose we have two functions and . We say that is the inverse function of (denoted ) if if and only if for all and .

Theorem 1. The inverse function exists if and only if is bijective

Theorem 2. A function is an inverse function of a function if and only if for all and for all .